Individual Rights vs. Collective Rights

The Individual and the Collective: Drawing the Line from Civil Liberties to Species Survival

Introduction: The Enduring Tension

The history of political and moral thought is, in many ways, the story of a single, enduring conflict: the struggle between the rights of the individual and the claims of the collective. This tension is the central axis around which our most profound questions of justice, freedom, and governance revolve. On one side stands the individual, conceived as a sovereign entity endowed with certain moral claims to freedom of action.[1] On the other stands the community—be it a society, a nation, or humanity itself—a group that also holds rights, not as a collection of individual claims, but as a whole.[1, 2] This fundamental dichotomy is not merely an academic curiosity; it is a fault line that runs through our most contentious contemporary debates.

This report will embark on a journey to explore the depths of this conflict. It will begin by excavating the philosophical bedrock of the debate, tracing the origins of our modern conceptions of rights to two competing traditions: the individual-centric liberalism born of the Enlightenment and the community-focused communitarianism that rose in response. It will demonstrate how one’s starting point—the primacy of the individual or the primacy of the community—largely determines one’s destination when confronting modern legal and ethical dilemmas.

From this theoretical foundation, the analysis will move to the practical realm, examining how this philosophical tension manifests in the real world. It will dissect three of the most acute battlegrounds where individual liberties clash with collective interests: the imposition of public health mandates versus the right to bodily autonomy; the expansion of state surveillance for national security versus the right to privacy; and the regulation of hate speech to protect group dignity versus the right to free expression.

Ethan Drake

Finally, this exploration will push these frameworks to their absolute breaking point. It will construct an extreme hypothetical scenario—a post-extinction event where the survival of the human species hangs in the balance—to ask the ultimate question. When the collective good is the very continuation of humanity, are there any individual rights that remain inviolable? Where is the line drawn when it is tested not by convenience or policy, but by existence itself? Through this crucible, we can hope to gain a clearer, if more unsettling, understanding of the principles we hold and the true cost of their application.


Part I: The Philosophical Divide: Individualism vs. Community

How a society resolves conflicts between the individual and the group is rarely a matter of spontaneous calculation. Instead, these resolutions are often the logical consequence of deeply embedded philosophical commitments. The answer to a question like “Should we mandate vaccines?” is frequently predetermined by the answer to a much more fundamental question: “What is a person, and what is a community?” Two major traditions offer starkly different answers, creating the philosophical divide that shapes our political world.

Section 1: The Primacy of the Individual: The Liberal Tradition

The dominant political philosophy of the modern West is liberalism, a tradition whose central premise is the moral and political primacy of the individual.[3, 4] In this view, the individual is the fundamental unit of analysis. Society is not an organism with its own will or rights; it is a collection of individuals who associate for their mutual benefit.[5, 6] Rights, therefore, are not gifts from the state or the community. They are inherent, pre-political, and inalienable, possessed by people simply by virtue of being human.[7, 8, 9, 10, 11] The very purpose of forming a government, according to this tradition, is not to create rights but to secure the rights that individuals already possess.[5, 12, 13]

Enlightenment Foundations

This powerful conception of rights has its roots in the intellectual ferment of the Enlightenment. The English philosopher John Locke (1632–1704) is a pivotal figure, arguing that all individuals in a “state of nature” possess natural rights to “Life, Liberty and Property”.[13, 14, 15] Central to Locke’s philosophy is the principle of self-ownership: “Every man has a property in his own person. This nobody has a right to, but himself”.[11, 16] This self-ownership is the foundation of all other rights. Because you own yourself, you own your labor. By mixing your labor with the unowned resources of the world, you come to own property.[11, 14] This establishes a robust sphere of personal autonomy and a moral barrier against interference from others.

The German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) provided a different but equally influential foundation for individual rights. For Kant, rights are grounded not in self-ownership but in the unique status of human beings as rational agents capable of moral reasoning.[7, 17] This capacity for reason endows every individual with an intrinsic worth, or “dignity.” From this dignity flows Kant’s famous Categorical Imperative, one formulation of which commands that we must always treat humanity, whether in our own person or in the person of another, as an end in itself, and never merely as a means to an end.[18] This principle creates a powerful deontological (duty-based) prohibition against sacrificing or using individuals for some larger collective goal, as doing so would treat them as mere instruments, violating their fundamental dignity.[19]

The Social Contract

These philosophical ideas found their political expression in social contract theory. Thinkers like Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau argued that legitimate government is formed through a “social contract,” an agreement among free individuals to leave the state of nature and live together under a set of common rules for the common good.[13] Crucially, the government created by this contract is not all-powerful. Its legitimacy is derived entirely from the “consent of the governed” and is conditional upon its success in protecting the pre-existing rights of the individuals who formed it.[13] The U.S. Declaration of Independence is perhaps the most famous articulation of this idea, asserting it as a “self-evident” truth that governments are instituted to secure inalienable rights and that when a government fails in this duty, “it is the Right of the People to alter or to abolish it”.[5, 9]

Modern Libertarianism

Modern libertarianism extends the classical liberal tradition to its most consistent conclusion. Libertarians argue that if individuals are self-owners with rights to life, liberty, and property, then the only legitimate function of a state is the “minimal” one of protecting those rights from force and fraud.[3, 11, 20] Any state action that goes beyond this—whether it’s redistributing wealth, regulating personal behavior for one’s own good (paternalism), or providing social services—is an unjust use of coercion and a violation of individual rights.[20] For a libertarian, there is no “collective” or “society” that can have claims against the individual. Society is simply a “spontaneous order” that emerges from the voluntary interactions of millions of people.[3] The concept of a “collective right” that could override an individual right is seen as a dangerous fiction, often used to justify state overreach.[5, 12]

This philosophical framework does more than just prioritize individual rights; it shapes the very understanding of what a “collective” is. It is not seen as a moral entity in its own right, but as a simple aggregation of individuals.[2] This ontological claim—about what a group is—is the direct source of the liberal normative claim about how a group should be treated. If a community is nothing more than the sum of its parts, then it cannot possess rights that are superior to or independent of the rights of those parts. As Thomas Jefferson articulated, “the rights of the whole can be no more than the sum of the rights of theindividuals”.[4] This framing means that any apparent conflict between an “individual right” and a “collective right” is, for a liberal, a false choice. The conflict is actually between the clear, tangible, pre-political right of a living person and a derivative, politically constructed claim made on behalf of an abstract entity. In such a contest, the individual is almost always destined to win.

Section 2: The Primacy of the Community: The Communitarian Response

Beginning in the latter half of the 20th century, a powerful critique of the liberal individualist tradition emerged under the banner of communitarianism. Communitarian thinkers argue that liberalism is built upon a flawed and impoverished understanding of human nature.[6, 21] They contend that the liberal vision of the autonomous, “unencumbered” self—an individual who exists prior to and independent of their social roles and attachments—is a philosophical fiction.[22] Instead, they argue for the primacy of the community in shaping who we are and how we ought to live.

The Socially Embedded Self

Philosophers such as Michael Sandel, Charles Taylor, and Amitai Etzioni are central figures in this critique.[21, 22, 23] They argue that individuals are not isolated atoms who enter society through a voluntary contract; rather, we are “socially embedded” from birth.[6, 23] Our identities are largely shaped and constituted by the communities we are a part of: our families, our cultures, our religious traditions, and our nations.[6, 22] These attachments are not mere preferences we choose; they are integral to who we are. To attempt to reason about justice or rights by abstracting ourselves from this social context—as John Rawls famously proposed with his “veil of ignorance”—is, for a communitarian, a philosophically incoherent exercise.[6] Because our identity is constructed through these social relations, there is no coherent way to formulate individual rights or interests in abstraction from them.[6]

The Common Good

Flowing from this conception of the self is a different vision of politics. If our well-being is inextricably tied to the health of our communities, then a just society cannot be neutral about the good life. It must be actively concerned with nurturing the “common good” and sustaining the shared values and practices that give our lives meaning.[21, 24, 25] This does not necessarily mean trampling on individuals, but it does mean that individual rights must be understood and balanced against our responsibilities to the communities that sustain us.[21, 26] The goal is to find a balance between individual autonomy and the interests of the community.[6]

Types of Communitarianism

This broad philosophy encompasses a spectrum of views. At one end lies Authoritarian Communitarianism, a model sometimes associated with East Asian societies like Singapore and China. This view explicitly prioritizes social harmony and the needs of the collective over individual autonomy and rights, viewing individuals as finding their primary meaning through contribution to the social whole.[24, 25]

A more moderate form is Responsive Communitarianism, most closely associated with Amitai Etzioni. This approach does not seek to abolish individual rights but to re-contextualize them. It argues that rights and responsibilities are two sides of the same coin and that a good society must attend to both.[24] Responsive communitarianism holds that while individual rights are a core value, they are not absolute. They can be limited when there is a “compelling interest” that serves the common good, so long as the limitation is carefully designed and respects the core values of autonomy as much as possible.[25]

Collective Rights in Practice

This communitarian worldview provides the philosophical grounding for the concept of genuine collective rights. These are rights held by a group as such and cannot be reduced to the sum of the rights of its individual members.[2, 27] Examples include the right of an indigenous people to self-determination, the right of a cultural minority to preserve its language, or the right of a nation to its traditional lands.[27, 28, 29] From a communitarian perspective, protecting these groups is essential because the well-being and identity of the individuals within them depend on the flourishing of the group’s shared culture and way of life.[12, 29]

The fundamental clash between liberalism and communitarianism, therefore, is not merely about policy preferences but about ontology and epistemology: What is a person? and How do we discover what is just? Where liberalism sees an “unencumbered self” that exists prior to its goals and attachments, communitarianism sees a “socially embedded” self whose identity is constituted by those very attachments.[22] This leads to a profound divergence in method. The liberal asks, “What principles would a free and rational individual, abstracted from their particular circumstances, consent to?” This method prioritizes universal, abstract reason. The communitarian, in contrast, argues that this is the wrong question. Because we are embedded beings, justice cannot be found by stepping outside our communities. It must be discovered from within our shared traditions, values, and understandings.[22] The communitarian asks, “What practices and institutions will sustain the health of the communities that are essential for human flourishing?” This focus on context and shared meaning explains why the two traditions arrive at such different conclusions on everything from the family to the nation-state.

Table 1: A Comparative Framework of Rights Philosophies

To crystallize the foundational differences between these two opposing worldviews, the following table provides a direct comparison of their core tenets. This framework serves as a reference point for understanding how these abstract philosophies translate into the concrete legal and ethical conflicts explored in the subsequent sections.

FeatureLiberalism / LibertarianismCommunitarianism
Primary Moral UnitThe Individual [3, 4]The Community [22, 25]
Source of RightsNature, Reason, Self-Ownership (Pre-political) [7, 11, 13]Social Context, Membership, Shared Understandings [6, 22]
View on the SelfThe “Unencumbered” Self; Autonomous Chooser [22]The “Socially Embedded” Self; Constituted by Attachments [6, 22]
Role of GovernmentTo Protect Individual Rights and Liberty [3, 5]To Nurture the Common Good and Sustain Community [21, 24]
Core ValueAutonomy, Liberty [20]Solidarity, Responsibility [21, 23]
Key ThinkersLocke, Kant, Mill, Nozick [11, 13, 17, 18]Aristotle, Hegel, Sandel, Taylor, Etzioni [21, 23, 25]

Part II: The Tension in Practice: Where the Line is Drawn Today

The abstract philosophical divide between individualism and communitarianism is not confined to the pages of academic journals. It is the driving force behind many of the most contentious legal and political issues of our time. In this section, we examine three specific arenas where the rights of the individual collide with the perceived needs of the collective, revealing how different societies attempt to draw a line between them.

Section 3: Public Health vs. Bodily Autonomy: The Case of Vaccine Mandates

Perhaps no recent issue has thrown the conflict between individual rights and the collective good into sharper relief than that of vaccine mandates. This debate represents a classic clash between the state’s responsibility to protect public health and the individual’s fundamental right to bodily autonomy and informed consent.[30, 31, 32]

The Collective Argument (Communitarian/Utilitarian)

The legal foundation for public health mandates in the United States was established over a century ago in the landmark Supreme Court case Jacobson v. Massachusetts (1905). During a smallpox outbreak, the Court upheld the state’s authority to require vaccination, establishing the crucial precedent that individual liberty is not absolute and can be constitutionally restricted to protect the community from an epidemic.[30, 33, 34] The Court reasoned that a society based on a social contract has a right to protect itself from existential threats.

This legal principle is supported by two powerful ethical concepts. The first is the “Tragedy of the Commons.” Public health officials argue that a high vaccination rate creates a collective good—”herd immunity”—that protects everyone, especially the most vulnerable who cannot be vaccinated.[35] An individual who chooses to remain unvaccinated while still benefiting from the protection afforded by others is acting as a “free-rider.” If too many individuals make this self-interested choice, the collective resource of herd immunity is depleted, leading to preventable outbreaks. Mandates are thus seen as a necessary tool to prevent this “tragedy”.[35, 36]

The second concept is that of a social contract. This view suggests that there is an implicit agreement among citizens to accept minor burdens, such as vaccination, in exchange for the immense benefit of living in a society protected from devastating infectious diseases.[35] This is not just about self-protection but about a duty to protect others in the community.[37]

The Individual Argument (Liberal/Libertarian)

Opponents of mandates ground their arguments in the liberal tradition’s emphasis on individual sovereignty. The core principle is bodily autonomy: the right of each person to control their own body and make their own healthcare decisions.[30, 31, 38] This right is seen as a direct extension of Lockean self-ownership. From this perspective, forcing a person to accept a medical intervention against their will is a profound violation of their most basic liberty, regardless of the purported collective benefit.[38]

Closely linked to this is the principle of informed consent, a cornerstone of modern medical ethics. This principle requires that patients be given all relevant information about a medical procedure and be free to accept or refuse it without coercion.[31, 38] Mandates, by introducing penalties for refusal (such as loss of employment or exclusion from school), are seen as a form of coercion that vitiates true consent. From a libertarian viewpoint, such state action is a gross overreach of government power into the private lives of individuals.[38]

The Balancing Act

In practice, most legal systems attempt to strike a balance. Even under the Jacobson precedent, the state’s power is not unlimited. Courts and public health ethicists often employ a proportionality analysis, asking whether the mandate is the “least restrictive” means necessary to achieve the public health goal.[31, 34] This involves weighing the severity of the public health threat against the degree of infringement on individual liberty. This balancing act is also evident in debates over the scope of medical and religious exemptions, with courts generally holding that such exemptions can be limited when they pose a direct threat to public safety.[30, 33]

The legal and ethical justification for mandates is not a static, on-off switch; it is a dynamic calculation highly sensitive to the perceived magnitude of the threat. The strong deference to public health authority in Jacobson occurred in the context of smallpox, a disease with a terrifyingly high mortality rate. The collective threat was so immense that the individual’s claim to liberty was heavily outweighed. The debates surrounding COVID-19 mandates were far more contentious, in part because the nature of the threat altered the proportionality calculation for different segments of the population. For a healthy young person, the personal risk of severe disease was statistically low, while the vaccine, like any medical intervention, carried its own small but non-zero risks.[38] This shift in the individual’s side of the risk-benefit analysis made the case for a universal mandate less compelling for some.

Furthermore, the public health argument for mandates is strongest when vaccination prevents not only disease in the individual but also transmission to others, thereby contributing to the collective good of herd immunity. When evidence suggests that a vaccine primarily reduces the severity of symptoms rather than preventing infection and spread, the “tragedy of the commons” argument is weakened.[36, 38] The decision to vaccinate becomes less of a contribution to a collective shield and more of a personal health choice, strengthening the argument for individual autonomy. This demonstrates that the debate is not simply about whether the state has the power to act, but about the specific factual and scientific conditions under which that power can be ethically and proportionally exercised.

Section 4: National Security vs. The Right to Privacy: The Surveillance State

In the digital age, another stark conflict has emerged between the state’s duty to provide national security—a quintessential collective good—and the individual’s fundamental right to privacy.[39, 40, 41]

The Collective Argument (The Security Imperative)

In the wake of catastrophic events like the September 11th attacks, governments around the world dramatically expanded their surveillance powers. In the U.S., legislation such as the USA PATRIOT Act gave intelligence agencies broad new authority to collect vast amounts of data on citizens and non-citizens alike, often without a traditional warrant.[39, 42] The justification for these measures is fundamentally utilitarian and communitarian: the state has a primary duty to protect its population from existential threats like terrorism. The potential harm of another major attack is considered so immense that it outweighs the less tangible harm of infringing on the privacy of millions of individuals.[39] In this view, privacy is not an absolute right but one that must be balanced against the collective need for safety and security.

The Individual Argument (The Right to be Let Alone)

The counterargument is rooted in foundational constitutional and human rights principles. In the United States, the Fourth Amendment protects individuals from “unreasonable searches and seizures” and generally requires the government to obtain a warrant based on probable cause before intruding into a person’s private life.[39, 42] Critics argue that mass, warrantless surveillance programs, which collect data on millions of innocent people, are a clear violation of this constitutional safeguard.[43]

This right is also enshrined in international law. Article 17 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) establishes a universal human right to be free from “arbitrary or unlawful interference with his privacy”.[44] This framework requires that any state surveillance must not only be lawful but also necessary and proportionate to a legitimate aim.

Beyond the legal arguments, opponents of mass surveillance warn of its “chilling effect” on a free society. When individuals believe their communications are being monitored, they may become hesitant to express dissenting opinions, associate with controversial groups, or engage in political activism. This self-censorship can slowly erode the open discourse that is essential for a healthy democracy.[39, 41, 43]

The Digital Dilemma

Modern technology has exponentially increased the stakes of this conflict. The state’s ability to collect, store, and analyze personal data is now virtually limitless. This has created new challenges for legal frameworks designed in a pre-digital era. International law, for example, struggles to apply concepts like “effective control” to borderless digital communications, often resulting in a system where foreign nationals have far fewer privacy protections than citizens, even though the technology of surveillance makes such distinctions increasingly meaningless.[44]

A structural asymmetry exists within this conflict that heavily favors the expansion of state power. The arguments for enhancing security are typically made by the state, often relying on classified information about low-probability but high-impact threats that the public cannot independently verify.[44] This appeals to a visceral and easily understood fear of catastrophic violence. In contrast, the harms of privacy loss are diffuse, incremental, and often abstract. They involve the slow erosion of liberty, the creation of a “chilling effect,” and the potential for future abuse of collected data.[41, 43] In the political arena, the immediate fear of a terrorist attack often proves more potent than the long-term concern about data collection.

This dynamic creates what can be described as a “one-way ratchet.” As technology advances, the state’s capacity for surveillance grows. In moments of crisis, such as the aftermath of a terrorist attack, these powers are expanded through legislation like the PATRIOT Act.[39, 42] Once granted, however, these powers are rarely relinquished. They become entrenched in the state’s security apparatus, normalizing a new, lower level of individual privacy. The “temporary” emergency measure becomes a permanent feature of the political landscape, permanently shifting the balance between the individual and the collective.

Section 5: Freedom of Expression vs. Collective Dignity: The Hate Speech Debate

The debate over hate speech forces a direct confrontation between one of the most cherished individual rights—freedom of expression—and the collective’s interest in protecting the dignity, equality, and safety of its members, particularly those from vulnerable or marginalized groups. Different democratic societies have resolved this conflict in fundamentally different ways, revealing their deepest philosophical commitments.

The U.S. Approach (Individualism Maximized)

The United States offers the world’s most robust legal protection for speech, including speech that is widely considered hateful. The First Amendment to the Constitution, as interpreted by the Supreme Court, does not contain a “hate speech” exception.[45, 46, 47] The prevailing legal doctrine, famously articulated by Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, is that the Constitution protects “freedom for the thought that we hate”.[45] The American view is that the proper response to hateful ideas is not government censorship but “more speech”—counter-protest, debate, and condemnation from fellow citizens.[45]

Under this framework, the government can only restrict speech in a few very narrow, well-defined categories. The most relevant of these is the “incitement” standard, established in Brandenburg v. Ohio (1969). This test holds that speech can be punished only if it is “directed to inciting or producing imminent lawless action and is likely to incite or produce such action”.[46, 48, 49] This is an extremely high bar to meet. Other unprotected categories include “true threats” of violence and discriminatory harassment in specific contexts (like the workplace or schools), but the general expression of hateful ideas in the public square is constitutionally protected.[45, 47, 49]

The Canadian/European Approach (Balancing Rights)

In stark contrast, many other Western democracies, including Canada and most European nations, have adopted a balancing approach. The Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms provides a clear example. While Section 2 of the Charter guarantees “freedom of thought, belief, opinion and expression,” this right is immediately qualified by Section 1, which states that all Charter rights are subject to “such reasonable limits prescribed by law as can be demonstrably justified in a free and democratic society”.[50, 51, 52, 53, 54]

This “reasonable limits” clause is the philosophical and legal engine that allows for the regulation of hate speech. Canadian law criminalizes the public incitement of hatred against identifiable groups. The rationale is that such speech does more than just offend; it harms the collective by undermining social harmony, eroding the dignity of minority groups, and creating a climate of fear and discrimination.[50, 55] This approach explicitly balances the individual’s right to expression against the collective’s right to a society where all members are treated with equal concern and respect.

The Central Question of “Harm”

Ultimately, the transatlantic divide on hate speech hinges on the definition of “harm.” The American legal tradition, in this context, defines harm very narrowly, largely confining it to direct, tangible, and immediate physical consequences, such as violence.[48] The Canadian and European models adopt a broader definition, recognizing that speech can inflict profound psychological and social harm by vilifying, dehumanizing, and marginalizing entire groups of people.[56] This broader understanding of harm justifies placing “reasonable limits” on expression to protect the collective good of a tolerant and inclusive society.

A country’s legal framework for hate speech acts as a powerful diagnostic tool, revealing its core political philosophy. The American system, with its near-absolute protection for speech, demonstrates a profound, historically rooted distrust of government power. The primary fear is that any authority granted to the state to censor “hate speech” will inevitably be abused to silence unpopular political dissent—a “slippery slope” that could lead to tyranny.[45] The system is therefore designed to protect the individual dissenter at all costs, even when that dissenter’s message is repugnant. The risk it is most willing to tolerate is the social harm caused by hateful ideas.

The Canadian system, with its explicit balancing mechanism in Section 1 of the Charter, reflects a more communitarian philosophy and a greater trust in the state’s ability to act as a neutral arbiter between competing rights.[52, 54] It acknowledges that rights are not absolute and must be reconciled with one another to serve the common good. This framework is designed to protect the social fabric and the dignity of vulnerable groups. The risk it is most willing to tolerate is the potential for the state to occasionally err in its balancing act. This is not a mere legal disagreement; it is a fundamental philosophical divergence on the primary purpose of a rights-protecting constitution. Is its main function to erect a shield between the individual and the state, or to provide a blueprint for a just, inclusive, and harmonious society?


Part III: The Ultimate Test Case: An Extinction Scenario

Having explored the philosophical foundations and practical applications of the conflict between individual and collective rights, we now turn to a thought experiment designed to push these concepts to their absolute limit. Hypothetical scenarios, particularly extreme ones, serve as philosophical crucibles. They are not meant as practical guides for the future but as diagnostic tools that strip away the complexities of ordinary life to isolate our most fundamental moral principles. By placing our ethical frameworks under unbearable stress, we can see where they bend, where they break, and what they reveal about our deepest commitments.

Section 6: Framing the Hypothetical: The Last Fertile Men

Imagine a future scenario of unparalleled catastrophe. A novel virus, a radiological event, or a targeted bioweapon has swept across the globe, with a devastatingly specific effect: it has rendered nearly all human males permanently sterile. Scientific and medical authorities, after a global survey, confirm that only a tiny handful of men—perhaps a few dozen scattered across the planet—remain fertile. The human species, Homo sapiens, is now on the brink of biological extinction. The survival of humanity itself depends entirely on the reproductive capacity of this small, isolated group.

In response, a reconstituted global authority or a consortium of surviving states enacts an emergency protocol. To ensure the continuation of the species and maximize the chances of creating a viable, genetically diverse next generation, these last fertile men are to be conscripted into a mandatory reproduction program. They will be compelled, through whatever means necessary, to provide genetic material to be used for impregnating a designated pool of fertile women.

The stakes of this scenario are absolute. On one side is the collective good, defined in its most ultimate sense: the prevention of the extinction of the human species. This is not merely a matter of public health, national security, or social harmony; it is the preservation of all potential future human lives and the continuation of the human story.[57, 58, 59] On the other side is the individual right, also in its most profound form. The mandate would constitute a total violation of the men’s most fundamental rights: their bodily autonomy and integrity, their reproductive freedom, the right to choose their own partners and form their own families, and their right not to be treated as mere biological instruments for a collective purpose.[31, 38, 60, 61, 62] It represents the complete subjugation of the individual to a biological imperative. The question is stark: Can any individual right be so absolute as to justify the extinction of the species?

Section 7: A Utilitarian Calculus: The Greatest Good for the Greatest Number?

At first glance, the ethical theory of utilitarianism seems to provide a clear and decisive answer. Utilitarianism, in its classic form, holds that the morally correct action is the one that produces the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people.[18, 63] It is a form of consequentialism, meaning it judges actions based on their outcomes.[63]

The Prima Facie Argument

Applying this framework to the extinction scenario, the calculation appears straightforward. The “good” produced by the mandatory reproduction program is the continuation of the human species—potentially billions upon billions of future lives, with all their attendant happiness, discovery, and flourishing. The “harm” produced is the profound suffering, loss of liberty, and violation of dignity inflicted upon a few dozen men. When weighing the immense, almost infinite good of species survival against the terrible but finite harm to a small group, a simple utilitarian calculus would almost certainly favor the mandate. The action, however horrific for the individuals involved, produces the greatest good for the greatest number and is therefore the morally required choice.[63, 64]

Complicating the Calculus: The Value of Extinction

However, this seemingly simple calculation rests on a monumental and highly contestable assumption: that the continuation of the human species is, in fact, a “good” to be maximized. The field of philosophy has produced powerful arguments that challenge this very premise, and these arguments threaten to collapse the entire utilitarian justification for the mandate.

The most direct challenge comes from antinatalism, a philosophical position most famously articulated by David Benatar. Benatar argues that coming into existence is always a serious harm. This is due to an asymmetry between pleasure and pain: the presence of pain is bad, and the presence of pleasure is good. However, the absence of pain is good, even if no one is there to enjoy it, while the absence of pleasure is not bad unless there is someone who is being deprived of it. Because every life contains a great deal of pain and suffering, and because non-existence is free from this harm, Benatar concludes that it is always better never to have been born. From this perspective, human extinction is not a catastrophe to be avoided but a laudable goal, as it would prevent the creation of countless future lives filled with inevitable suffering.[65, 66, 67]

A related, though less extreme, argument questions whether we have any moral obligation to create future people at all. Philosophers like Johann Frick and Elizabeth Finneron-Burns argue that while we have reasons to make existing people happy, we do not have a corresponding reason to “make happy people”.[68, 69] Merely possible future people cannot be harmed by their non-existence, as there is no one there to experience the burden of not being born. Therefore, we have no moral duty to bring them into existence, no matter how wonderful their lives might be.[68]

If either of these philosophical positions is accepted, the utilitarian case for the forced reproduction mandate evaporates. If human existence is a net harm (the antinatalist view), then the mandate is monstrous, as it perpetuates a cycle of suffering. If the value of future existence is simply zero (the “no obligation to create” view), then the only morally relevant factor in the equation is the certain and terrible harm being inflicted on the fertile men. The “greatest good” would then be to respect their rights and allow humanity to go extinct peacefully. The utilitarian framework, which appeared to offer the strongest justification for sacrificing the few for the many, is revealed to be surprisingly fragile. Its conclusion is entirely dependent on a prior, non-utilitarian value judgment: that human existence itself is a good worth preserving. Utilitarianism cannot generate this premise on its own; it can only perform a calculation based on the values it is given. This exposes a hidden dependency in what purports to be a self-sufficient ethical system.

Section 8: A Deontological Stand: The Inviolability of the Individual

Where utilitarianism focuses on outcomes, deontological ethics focuses on duties and rules. Rooted in the philosophy of Immanuel Kant, deontology asserts that certain actions are intrinsically right or wrong, regardless of their consequences.[19] From this perspective, the extinction scenario is not a complex calculation but a clear moral test.

The Kantian Imperative

The mandatory reproduction program is a quintessential violation of the Kantian Categorical Imperative. It treats the fertile men not as persons with their own goals, dignity, and life plans, but as mere biological instruments—a means to the end of species propagation.[18] Their bodies and reproductive capacities are being used as a resource for the collective. For a deontologist, this is a categorical moral wrong. It is a violation of the inherent dignity that each person possesses by virtue of their rationality, a dignity that cannot be traded away for any amount of collective good.[19]

The Nature of Inalienable Rights

This perspective holds that certain rights, such as the right to self-ownership and bodily integrity, are inalienable. They are not granted by society and cannot be taken away by society, no matter how pressing the emergency.[11, 20] To violate such a fundamental right is to cross a moral line that should never be crossed. The argument is not that the men’s rights outweigh the survival of the species; it is that the two cannot be placed on the same scale. The right is a moral constraint on action, not an item in a cost-benefit analysis.

Is a Humanity Without Morality Worth Saving?

Deontology pushes the analysis to a deeper, more profound level. It forces us to ask: what, precisely, are we trying to save? If the answer is merely the biological species Homo sapiens—a particular arrangement of DNA—then the question is one of biological continuity. But if the answer is “humanity” in a moral sense—a community defined by its capacity for reason, dignity, and mutual respect—then the mandate becomes self-defeating.

A deontologist could argue that a community that would resort to such a measure, that would systematically rape and enslave a group of its members to ensure its own biological continuation, has already sacrificed its claim to the moral title of “humanity”.[59, 70] The very act of survival has destroyed the thing that made survival morally valuable in the first place. This reframes the entire dilemma. The choice is not between the rights of a few individuals and the existence of the species. It is a choice between upholding the foundational moral principles that define us as a moral community (and accepting the consequence of biological extinction) or abandoning those principles to perpetuate a biological lineage that has been stripped of its essential moral character.

Section 9: Seeking a Middle Ground: Proportionality and the Harm Principle in Extremis

Faced with the absolutism of deontology and the unsettling calculations of utilitarianism, one might turn to moderating principles designed to find a middle ground in conflicts of rights. However, the extinction scenario reveals the limits of these frameworks, showing them to be tools for a world that is not completely broken.

Proportionality

The principle of proportionality, central to human rights law, requires that any restriction on a right must be a “proportionate means of achieving a legitimate aim”.[71, 72] It demands a balancing of the individual’s rights against the interests of the community and requires that the “least restrictive option” be chosen.[71, 73]

This framework immediately breaks down when applied to the hypothetical. First, as established, whether species survival is a “legitimate aim” is itself a deeply contested philosophical question.[68, 69] Second, the concept of a “least restrictive option” becomes meaningless when the scenario posits that forced reproduction is the only option to avoid extinction. There are no less restrictive alternatives to compare. The balancing test, which is meant to weigh competing interests, becomes impossible. How does one balance the absolute right to bodily integrity against the “interest” of an infinite number of potential future people? The scales are incommensurable. Proportionality is a tool for navigating conflicts within a functioning society, not for justifying its forced continuation.

The Harm Principle

John Stuart Mill’s harm principle offers another potential path. It states that “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others”.[74, 75, 76] This principle is the cornerstone of classical liberalism’s defense of individual liberty.

Like proportionality, the harm principle falters in this extreme context. The crucial question is: who are the “others” being harmed by the men’s refusal to reproduce? The direct victims are potential people who do not yet exist. A strong philosophical argument can be made that one cannot harm a non-existent person by failing to bring them into existence.[68] If there is no person to experience the deprivation, there is no harm. If this is true, then the central condition of the harm principle is not met. The men’s refusal is a self-regarding act (in that it does not harm any existing person), and therefore society has no right to interfere. The principle was designed to regulate the interactions of existing individuals in a society, to prevent them from becoming a “nuisance to other people”.[76] It was not designed to compel the creation of a new society from scratch.

This scenario, therefore, acts as a form of reductio ad absurdum. It reveals that our most trusted ethical frameworks for mediating the relationship between the individual and the state are contingent on a background of relative normalcy. They presuppose a world with multiple choices, existing communities, and a shared social context. When that context is shattered by an existential threat, these principles lose their coherence, leaving us with only the raw, unmediated clash between the duty to maximize good and the duty to respect persons.


Part IV: Synthesis and Concluding Reflections

Section 10: Drawing the Line in Shifting Sands

The journey from the philosophical debates of the Enlightenment to a hypothetical struggle for species survival reveals a stark truth: the line between the rights of the individual and the needs of the collective is not a fixed, immutable boundary. It is a shifting, negotiated frontier, drawn and redrawn based on a society’s deepest philosophical commitments, its perception of threats, and its cultural context.

The analysis of public health, national security, and hate speech demonstrates this contingency. A society like the United States, founded on a deep-seated liberal individualism and a distrust of state power, will draw the line to provide maximum protection for individual autonomy, even at the cost of social friction or perceived risk. It will tolerate hateful speech to avoid the greater perceived danger of censorship and will view surveillance with inherent suspicion. In contrast, a society like Canada, with a constitutional framework that explicitly allows for the balancing of rights for the collective good, will draw the line differently. It will permit “reasonable limits” on expression to protect group dignity and will more readily accept infringements on liberty for the sake of public health, reflecting a more communitarian ethos. Neither line is inherently “correct”; each is the logical outcome of its foundational philosophy.

The line also shifts in response to the perceived magnitude of the threat. The state’s power to compel vaccination, largely accepted in the face of a high-mortality disease like smallpox, becomes far more contentious when the disease poses a lesser risk to large segments of the population. Surveillance powers that would be unthinkable in peacetime are readily granted in the aftermath of a catastrophic attack. The gravity of the collective need directly impacts the weight given to the individual’s claim to be free from interference.

The final, extreme thought experiment serves not as a guide for post-apocalyptic governance, but as a lens to magnify these underlying principles. It forces us to confront the ultimate justifications for our political and ethical beliefs. The utilitarian, who seeks the greatest good, is forced to ask whether human existence is a “good” in itself—a question utilitarianism alone cannot answer. The deontologist, who champions the inviolable dignity of the person, is forced to ask whether a moral code that leads to extinction is a code worth following. The scenario reveals that even our most robust ethical systems have breaking points and are contingent on a world that has not fallen apart.

In the end, no simple formula can resolve the tension between the one and the many. The conflict is enduring because both sides represent a profound moral truth. We are individuals, each with a single, precious life and a claim to dignity and autonomy. We are also social beings, nested within communities that give our lives meaning and whose survival is a precondition for our own flourishing. The irresolvable nature of the final dilemma is not a sign of philosophical failure. It is a reflection of the human condition itself, caught forever between the dignity we owe to each unique person and the survival we desire for the collective that is our species.


Works cited

  1. en.wikipedia.org, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Individual_and_group_rights#:~:text=An%20individual%20right%20is%20a,than%20individually%20by%20its%20members.
  2. Group Rights (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), accessed July 19, 2025, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-group/
  3. Key Concepts of Libertarianism | Cato Institute, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.cato.org/commentary/key-concepts-libertarianism
  4. Individualism: A Libertarianism.org Guide, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.libertarianism.org/topics/individualism
  5. Individual and group rights – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Individual_and_group_rights
  6. Communitarianism – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Communitarianism
  7. Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights – Number Analytics, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.numberanalytics.com/blog/philosophical-foundations-human-rights
  8. Cruft R, Liao SM & Renzo M (2015) The Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights: An Overview. In, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.stir.ac.uk/research/hub/file/567678
  9. The Enlightenment and Human Rights – Facing History & Ourselves, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.facinghistory.org/resource-library/who-human
  10. Rights or Individual Rights – Annenberg Classroom, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.annenbergclassroom.org/glossary_term/rights-or-individual-rights/
  11. Libertarianism | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed July 19, 2025, https://iep.utm.edu/libertar/
  12. How “Collective Human Rights” Undermine Individual Human Rights, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.heritage.org/global-politics/report/how-collective-human-rights-undermine-individual-human-rights
  13. Enlightenment Social Contract Theory – Bill of Rights Institute, accessed July 19, 2025, https://billofrightsinstitute.org/essays/background-essay-the-enlightenment-and-social-contract-theory
  14. oercommons.org, accessed July 19, 2025, https://oercommons.org/courseware/lesson/87905/student/?section=2#:~:text=Locke%20is%20particularly%20known%20for,property%20is%20derived%20from%20labor.
  15. What Is the Enlightenment and How Did It Transform Politics? – CFR Education, accessed July 19, 2025, https://education.cfr.org/learn/reading/what-enlightenment-and-how-did-it-transform-politics
  16. Viewpoint: Common Good vs Greater Good; One is Often Good, One is Evil – Frontier Institute, accessed July 19, 2025, https://frontierinstitute.org/viewpoint-common-good-vs-greater-good-one-is-often-good-one-is-evil/
  17. Age of Enlightenment – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Age_of_Enlightenment
  18. Thinking Ethically – Markkula Center for Applied Ethics – Santa Clara University, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.scu.edu/ethics/ethics-resources/ethical-decision-making/thinking-ethically/
  19. Ethics Theories: Utilitarianism Vs. Deontological Ethics – Christian Research Institute, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.equip.org/articles/ethics-theories-utilitarianism-vs-deontological-ethics/
  20. Libertarianism – Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed July 19, 2025, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/libertarianism/
  21. Understanding Communitarianism in Law – Number Analytics, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.numberanalytics.com/blog/ultimate-guide-communitarianism-philosophy-law
  22. Communitarianism (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy), accessed July 19, 2025, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/communitarianism/
  23. Understanding Communitarianism in Ethics – Number Analytics, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.numberanalytics.com/blog/communitarianism-ethics-public-policy
  24. What Is Communitarianism? Definition and Main Theorists – ThoughtCo, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.thoughtco.com/communitarianism-definition-and-theories-5070063
  25. Communitarianism | Political Philosophy, Social Ethics & Community Values – Britannica, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.britannica.com/topic/communitarianism
  26. “Communitarianism” by Robert M. Ackerman – Florida State University, accessed July 19, 2025, https://ir.law.fsu.edu/lr/vol45/iss1/2/
  27. INDIVIDUAL V. COLLECTIVE RIGHTS 4.1. Introduction It is my view that protection of the right to cultural identity of minoritie – Brill, accessed July 19, 2025, https://brill.com/display/book/9789004233836/B9789004233836-s006.pdf
  28. What defines individual rights versus collective rights? – TutorChase, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.tutorchase.com/answers/ib/politics/what-defines-individual-rights-versus-collective-rights
  29. Individual vs Collective Rights Debate (2.4.1) | IB DP Global Politics HL Notes | TutorChase, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.tutorchase.com/notes/ib/global-politics/2-4-1-individual-vs-collective-rights-debate
  30. Vaccination Mandates and Civil Liberties, accessed July 19, 2025, https://digitalcommons.fau.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1018&context=ulj
  31. Ethical Issues in Mandating COVID-19 Vaccination for Health Care Personnel – PMC, accessed July 19, 2025, https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC8633920/
  32. How Bodily Autonomy Can Fail Against Vaccination Mandates; The Few vs. the Many, accessed July 19, 2025, https://engagedscholarship.csuohio.edu/jlh/vol37/iss2/7/
  33. WHY IS VACCINATION DIFFERENT? A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF RELIGIOUS EXEMPTIONS – Columbia Law Review, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.columbialawreview.org/content/why-is-vaccination-different-a-comparative-analysis-of-religious-exemptions/
  34. When Are Vaccine Mandates Appropriate? – AMA Journal of Ethics, accessed July 19, 2025, https://journalofethics.ama-assn.org/article/when-are-vaccine-mandates-appropriate/2020-01
  35. Chapter 13 – Vaccination Mandates: The Public Health … – CDC, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.cdc.gov/vaccines/imz-managers/guides-pubs/downloads/vacc_mandates_chptr13.pdf
  36. Five reasons why ‘my body, my choice’ doesn’t work for vaccines, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.gavi.org/vaccineswork/five-reasons-why-my-body-my-choice-doesnt-work-vaccines
  37. Individual freedoms versus collective responsibility: immunization decision-making in the face of occasionally competing values – PubMed Central, accessed July 19, 2025, https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC1592474/
  38. Mandating these vaccines violates a person’s bodily autonomy and strips a person of many basic human rights. How is it that on – DPBH, accessed July 19, 2025, https://dpbh.nv.gov/uploadedFiles/dpbhnvgov/content/Boards/BOH/Meetings/2021/PC%20240.pdf
  39. National Security vs. Individual Privacy – (Civil Rights and Civil Liberties) – Fiveable, accessed July 19, 2025, https://library.fiveable.me/key-terms/civil-rights-civil-liberties/national-security-vs-individual-privacy
  40. What is more important: our privacy or national security? – Alumni Mcmaster, accessed July 19, 2025, https://alumni.mcmaster.ca/s/1439/16/interior.aspx?sid=1439&gid=1&pgid=8281
  41. Surveillance vs. Privacy — Balancing Security and Freedom in Cybersecurity – Medium, accessed July 19, 2025, https://medium.com/@RocketMeUpCybersecurity/surveillance-vs-privacy-balancing-security-and-freedom-in-cybersecurity-3bada300616f
  42. Civil Liberties and Government Surveillance – Plural Policy, accessed July 19, 2025, https://pluralpolicy.com/blog/government-surveillance-civil-liberties/
  43. Privacy and Surveillance | American Civil Liberties Union, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.aclu.org/issues/national-security/privacy-and-surveillance
  44. Human Rights Extraterritoriality: The Right to Privacy and National …, accessed July 19, 2025, https://scholarship.law.gwu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=2562&context=faculty_publications
  45. Is Hate Speech Legal? | The Foundation for Individual Rights and Expression – FIRE, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.thefire.org/research-learn/hate-speech-legal
  46. Hate speech in the United States – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hate_speech_in_the_United_States
  47. What is hate speech, and is it protected by the First Amendment? – UW-Milwaukee, accessed July 19, 2025, https://uwm.edu/freespeech/faqs/what-is-hate-speech-and-is-it-protected-by-the-first-amendment/
  48. Hate Speech vs Free Speech – (Civil Rights and Civil Liberties) – Vocab, Definition, Explanations | Fiveable, accessed July 19, 2025, https://library.fiveable.me/key-terms/civil-rights-civil-liberties/hate-speech-vs-free-speech
  49. Frequently Asked Questions – Free Speech – Iowa State University, accessed July 19, 2025, https://freespeech.iastate.edu/faq
  50. The rights and freedoms the Charter protects – Department of Justice Canada, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.justice.gc.ca/eng/csj-sjc/rfc-dlc/ccrf-ccdl/rfcp-cdlp.html
  51. The Charter of Rights and Freedoms – Certificate in Law: Intro to Basic Legal Concepts, accessed July 19, 2025, https://guides.library.queensu.ca/basic-legal-concepts/charter-rights-freedoms
  52. Protesters need to understand: Canada’s Charter is not the U.S. Bill of Rights – Opinion by Professor Martha Jackman | National Association of Women and the Law, accessed July 19, 2025, https://nawl.ca/protesters-need-to-understand-canadas-charter-is-not-the-u-s-bill-of-rights-opinion-by-professor-martha-jackman/
  53. www.justice.gc.ca, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.justice.gc.ca/eng/csj-sjc/rfc-dlc/ccrf-ccdl/check/art1.html#:~:text=Provision,a%20free%20and%20democratic%20society.
  54. Charterpedia – Section 1 – Reasonable limits – Department of Justice Canada, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.justice.gc.ca/eng/csj-sjc/rfc-dlc/ccrf-ccdl/check/art1.html
  55. Section 1 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Section_1_of_the_Canadian_Charter_of_Rights_and_Freedoms
  56. John Stuart Mill’s Harm Principle and Free Speech: Expanding the Notion of Harm – Washington and Lee University School of Law Scholarly Commons, accessed July 19, 2025, https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/context/wlufac/article/1752/viewcontent/john_stuart_mill_s_harm_principle_and_free_speech_expanding_the_notion_of_harm_div.pdf
  57. If survival is the base instinct for any organism,then is it right for that to precede moral obligations? : r/askphilosophy – Reddit, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/askphilosophy/comments/b4x8a9/if_survival_is_the_base_instinct_for_any/
  58. CHARLES C. VERHAREN/DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY/ HOWARD UNIVERSITY EXCERPT FROM AUTHORS’ ACCEPTED VERSION OF “INTRODUCI, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/2015/02/11/survival-ethics-theory-verharen-excerpt-04-27-12.pdf
  59. The Ethics of Survival: Responsibility and Sacrifice in Environmental Ethics – Publishing at the Library, accessed July 19, 2025, https://journals.library.ualberta.ca/pandpr/index.php/pandpr/article/download/21169/16055/51959
  60. Trump on Abortion | American Civil Liberties Union, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.aclu.org/trump-on-abortion
  61. Changes Ahead: Abortion Policy Proposals Affecting Reproductive Medicine, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.asrm.org/advocacy-and-policy/reproductive-rights/summary-reports/changes-ahead-abortion-policy-proposals-affecting-reproductive-medicine/
  62. The Faces of US Pronatalism And the War on Women’s Rights – Part One, accessed July 19, 2025, https://populationmatters.org/news/2025/01/the-faces-of-u-s-pronatalism-and-the-war-on-womens-rights-part-one/
  63. Utilitarianism – Ethics Unwrapped – University of Texas at Austin, accessed July 19, 2025, https://ethicsunwrapped.utexas.edu/glossary/utilitarianism
  64. Violating rights for the greater good – (Ethics) – Vocab, Definition, Explanations | Fiveable, accessed July 19, 2025, https://library.fiveable.me/key-terms/ethics/violating-rights-for-the-greater-good
  65. en.wikipedia.org, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Human_extinction#:~:text=Some%20philosophers%20adopt%20the%20antinatalist,into%20existence%20in%20the%20future.
  66. Human extinction – Wikipedia, accessed July 19, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Human_extinction
  67. Bioethicist Pushes Human Extinction in Prestigious Journal | Discovery Institute, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.discovery.org/a/bioethicist-pushes-human-extinction-in-prestigious-journal/
  68. On the Wrongness of Human Extinction – Argumenta – Journal of Analytic Philosophy, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.argumenta.org/wp-content/uploads/2020/01/5-Argumenta-51-Simon-Beard-and-Patrick-Kaczmarek-On-the-Wrongness-of-Human-Extinction.pdf
  69. Does the value of rational activity explain the badness of human extinction? | The Philosophical Quarterly | Oxford Academic, accessed July 19, 2025, https://academic.oup.com/pq/advance-article/doi/10.1093/pq/pqaf003/8026073
  70. Ethics and Survival – Milton Fisk, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.miltonfisk.org/writings-in-progress/ethics-and-survival/
  71. What is proportionality? | British Institute of Human Rights, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.bihr.org.uk/get-informed/legislation-explainers/what-is-proportionality
  72. Proportionality Principle – SHRC – Equality & Human Rights Impact Assessment, accessed July 19, 2025, https://eqhria.scottishhumanrights.com/eqhriatrainingproportionality.html
  73. www.bihr.org.uk, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.bihr.org.uk/get-informed/legislation-explainers/what-is-proportionality#:~:text=The%20Principle%20of%20Proportionality,human%20rights%20to%20be%20justifiable.
  74. Mill’s concept of liberty and the harm principle | Political Philosophy Class Notes – Fiveable, accessed July 19, 2025, https://library.fiveable.me/political-philosophy/unit-7/mills-concept-liberty-harm-principle/study-guide/2l7XxDN1IiLAnVVy
  75. The Harm Principle – Unreasonable, accessed July 19, 2025, https://unreasonable.blog/liberty/harm.html
  76. Understanding Harm Principle in Law – Number Analytics, accessed July 19, 2025, https://www.numberanalytics.com/blog/harm-principle-in-law-and-morality